Next: 3.2 Integers and Rationals.
Up: 3. Induction and Integers
Previous: 3. Induction and Integers
  Index
3.1
Definition (Inductive set.)
Let
be a field. A subset
of
is
inductive
if it satisfies the two
conditions:
- i)
- .
- ii)
- for all ,
.
3.2
Examples.
and
are inductive sets in
.
Every field
is an inductive subset of itself.
If is an inductive subset of , then
etc. Hence every inductive set contains
If is an inductive subset of
, then
so the only inductive subset of
is
itself. The set
is an inductive subset in
.
3.3
Exercise.
Which of the following subsets of
are inductive?
3.4
Exercise.
- a)
- Find an inductive subset of
, such that
and
.
- b)
- Find an inductive subset of
, such that
and
.
3.5
Definition (Natural numbers in .)
Let
be a field, and let
. Then
is a
natural number in if
is in every inductive subset of
. The set of all natural numbers in
will
be denoted by
.
3.6
Example.
By the first example in
3.2, for every field
If
,
.
3.7
Remark.
By the definition of
,
is a subset of every inductive
subset of
, i.e.,
3.8
Theorem.
Let be a field. Then the set
of natural numbers in is an inductive
set.
Proof: Since is in every inductive set,
. Let be an inductive
subset of . Then for all ,
Hence
Hence
is inductive.
3.9
Remark.
We summarize the previous theorem and remark by saying
``
is the
smallest inductive subset of
."
is an inductive set, and it's a subset of
every other inductive set. You should expect that
(whatever ``
" might mean).
Proof: Let be a proposition form on
satisfying (3.11) and
(3.12). Let
I want to show that is inductive. Well, , by (3.11). Let
be any element in .
- Case 1.
-
- Case 2.
-
If , then is false, so
is true.
Thus
for all ,
This shows that is inductive. Since every inductive set contains
,
; i.e., for all
, is true.
3.13
Theorem.
Let be a field, and let be natural numbers in . Then and are in
.
Proof: Let be the proposition form on
defined by
Then says ``
" which is true. For all
,
By the induction theorem, is true for all
; i.e.,
Now define a proposition form on
by
Then says ``
" which is true.
For all
,
By the induction theorem, is true for all
; i.e.,
3.14
Theorem.
Let be an ordered field. Then for all
, we have
Proof: Define a proposition form on
by
Clearly is true. let
. To show that
, I'll show that
and that
. Well
and
Hence
, and by induction is true for all
.
3.15
Corollary.
Let be an ordered field. Then there is no element
such that
3.16
Lemma.
Let be an ordered field. Then
|
(3.17) |
Proof: Define a proposition form on
by
|
(3.18) |
Then is true. Let
.
To show that
, I'll show
that
and that (
. Well,
and
Hence
, and by induction, is true for all
.
3.19
Theorem.
Let be an ordered field
and let
. Then
Proof: For each
define a proposition form on
by
I'll show that for each
, is true for all
.
Now says
`` or " which is true, since
.
Now let
. To show that
, I'll show that
and that
By the previous lemma
Also
This completes the proof that
, so by induction is
true for all
.
3.20
Corollary.
Let be an ordered field, and let
.
If , then
.
Proof: Suppose
|
(3.22) |
Then
Since , the previous theorem says
. This contradicts corollary
3.15, so (3.22) is false.
3.23
Theorem (Least Element Principle.)
Let be an ordered field. Then every non-empty subset of
contains
a least element, i.e. if
, then there is some element
such that for all .
Proof: I will show that if is a subset of
having no least
element, then .
Let be a subset of
having no least element. For each
define
a proposition by
Now , since if were in it would be a least element for
. Hence all elements in are greater than , and is true.
Now let be a generic element of
. Then
since if were in , it would be a least element for .
Thus
and by induction, is true for all
.
It follows that , since if contained an element , then
would say that .
3.24
Exercise.
A
Let
be an ordered field. Show that
there is a non-empty subset
of
that has no smallest element, i.e.
there is a set
such that
3.25
Example.
Let
be an ordered field. Let
be the proposition form on
defined by
|
(3.26) |
Then for all
Hence
for all
. Now note:
Since
is false, I cannot apply the induction theorem. Notice that when I
prove
I do
not assume that
is true. (Although I
might as well, since I know
is true if
is false.)
Proof: Let be the proposition form on
defined by
(observe that
so is
defined). Then , so is true by (3.28). For all
,
so
By the induction theorem, is true for all
; i.e., is true
for all
. To complete the proof, I need to show that
It is clear that
To show the opposite inclusion, observe that if
and , then
, and by theorem 3.19,
.
3.30
Example.
Let
be an ordered field, and let
be the proposition form on
defined by
In example
3.25, we showed that
for all
and
that
is true. Hence, by our generalized induction theorem we can conclude
that
is true for all
with
.
3.31
Exercise.
Let
be a field
and let
. We say
is
even
if
for some
, and we say
is
odd if
for some
.
- a)
- What are the even numbers in
?
- b)
- What are the odd numbers in
?
3.32
Exercise.
A
- a)
- Let be a field. Prove that every element in
is either even or
odd. HINT: Let is even or is odd".
- b)
- Let be an ordered field. Prove that
no element of
is both even and odd. Why doesn't this contradict the result of exercise
3.31?
3.33
Note.
The question of whether to consider
to be a natural number is not
settled. Some authors start the natural numbers at
, other authors start them at
. It is interesting to note that Aristotle did not consider
to be a number.
for ``one" signifies a measure of some plurality, and ``
a number" signifies a measured plurality or a plurality of measures. Therefore, it is
also with good reason that unity is not a number; for neither is a measure measures,
but a measure is a principle, and so is unity .
[5, page 237, N, 1, 1088a5]
Zero was first recognized to be a number around the ninth century. According to
[31, page 185] Mahavira (ninth century)
noted that any number multiplied
by zero produces zero, and any number divided by zero remains unchanged! Bhaskara
(1114-1185) said that a number divided by is called an infinite quantity.
Although arguments that are essentially arguments by induction appear in
Euclid,
the
first clear statement of the induction principle is usually credited to Blaise
Pascal.
(1623-1662) who used induction to prove properties of Pascal's Triangle.[36, page
73]
I believe that the idea of defining the natural numbers to be things that are in
every inductive set should be credited to Giuseppe Peano [37, page 94, Axiom 9]. In.
1889, Peano gave a set of axioms for natural numbers
(starting with ), one of
which can be paraphrased as: If is any set, such that and for all
,
, then
.
Next: 3.2 Integers and Rationals.
Up: 3. Induction and Integers
Previous: 3. Induction and Integers
  Index